友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
飞读中文网 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

vill2-第11章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!



o prove personal villainage one had to prove villainage by birth。 Recognition of servile status in a court of record and reference to a deed are quite exceptional。     The coincidence in all these points against the party maintaining servitude is by no means casual; the courts proclaimed their leaning 'in favour of liberty' quite openly; and followed it in many instances besides those just quoted。 It was held; for instance; that in defending liberty every means ought to be admitted。 The counsel pleading for it sometimes set up two or three pleas against his adversary and declined to narrow his contention; thus transgressing the rules against duplicity of plea 'in favour of liberty。'* In the case of a stranger settling on the land; his liberty was always assumed; and the court declined to construe any uncertainty of condition against him。4 When villainage was pleaded in bar against a person out of the power of the lord; the special question was very often examined by a jury from the place where the person excepted to had been lately resident; and not by a jury from the country where he had been born。* This told against the lord; of course; because the jurors might often have very vague notions as to the previous condition of their new fellow…countryman。*     It would be impossible to say in what particular cases this partiality of the law is to be taken as a consequence of enlightened and humanitarian views making towards the liberation of the servile class; and in what cases it may be traced to the fact that an original element of freedom had been attracted into the constitution of villainage and was influencing its legal development despite any general theory of a servile character。 There is this to be noticed in any case; that most of the limitations we have been speaking of are found in full work at the very time when villainage was treated as slavery in the books。 One feature; perhaps the most important of all; is certainly not dependent on any progress of ideas; however complete the lord's power over the serf may have been; it was entirely bound up with the manorial organisation。 As soon as the villain had got out of its boundaries he was regularly treated as a free man and protected in the enjoyment of liberty so long as his servile status had not been proved。* Such protection was a legal necessity; a necessary complement to the warranty offered by the state to its real free men。 There could be no question of allowing the lord to seize on any person whom he thought fit to claim as his serf。 And; again; if the political power inherent in the manor gave the lord A great privileges and immunities as to the people living under his sway; this same manorial power began to tell against him as soon as such people had got under the sway of lord B or within the privileged town C The dependant could be effectually coerced only if he got back to his unfree nest again or through the means of such kinsfolk as he had left in the unfree nest。* And so the settlement of disputed rights connected with status brings home forcibly two important positions: first the theory of personal subjection is modified in its legal application by influence in favour of liberty; and next this influence is not to be traced exclusively to moral and intellectual progress; but must be accounted for to a great extent by peculiarities in the political structure of feudalism。     One point remains to be investigated in the institution of villainage; namely modes in which a villain might become free。 I have had occasion to notice the implied manumission which followed from a donation of land to a bondman and his heirs; which in process of time was extended to all contracts and concords between a lord and his serf。 A villain was freed also; as is well known; by remaining for a year and a day on the privileged soil of a crown manor or a chartered town。* As to direct manumission; its usual mode was the grant of a charter by which the lord renounced all rights as to the person of his villain。 Traces of other and more archaic customs may have survived in certain localities; but; if so; they were quite exceptional。 Manumission is one of the few subjects touched by Glanville in the doctrine of villainage; and he is very particular as to its conditions and effects。 He says that a serf cannot buy his freedom; because he has no money or goods of his own。 His liberty may be bought by a third person however; and his lord may liberate him as to himself; but not as regards third persons。 There seems to be a want of clearness in; if not some contradiction between these two last statements; because one does not see how manumission by a stranger could possibly be wider than that effected by the lord。 Again; the whole position of a freed man who remains a serf as regards everybody but his lord is very difficult to realize; even if one does not take the later view into account; which is exactly the reverse; namely that a villain is free against everybody but his lord。 I may be allowed to start a conjecture which will find some support in a later chapter; when we come to speak about the treatment of freedom and serfdom in manorial documents。 It seems to me that Glanville has in mind liberation de facto from certain duties and customs; such as agricultural work for instance; or the payment of merchet。 Such liberation would not amount to raising the status of a villain; although it would put him on a very different footing as to his lord。* However this may be; if from Glanville's times we come down to Bracton and to his authorities; we shall find all requirements changed; but distinct traces of the former view still lingering in occasional decisions and practices。 There are frequent cases of villains buying their freedom with their own money;* but the practice of selling them for manumission to a stranger is mentioned both in Bracton's Treatise* and in his Notebook。 A decision of 1226 distinctly repeats Glanville's teaching that a man may liberate his serf as to himself and not as to others。 The marginal note in the Notebook very appropriately protests against such a view; which is certainly quite inconsistent with later practice。* Such flagrant contradictions between authorities which are separated barely by some sixty or seventy years; and on points of primary importance too; can only tend to strengthen the inference previously drawn from other facts  that the law on the subject was by no means square and settled even by the time of Bracton; but was in every respect in a state of transition。

NOTES:

1。 Littleton; sect。 188。

2。 Bracton; ff。 5; 193; b。

3。 I need not say that there were very notable variations in the history of the Roman rule itself (cf for instance; Puchta; Institutionen; 211); but these do not concern us; as we are taking the Roman doctrine as broadly as it was taken by medieval lawyers。

4。 Mater certa est。 Gai。 Inst。 I。 82。 3 See Fitz。 Abr。 Villenage; pl。 5 (43 Edw。 III): 'Ou il allege bastardise pur ceo qe si son auncestor fuit bastard il ne puit estre villein; sinon par connusance。' There was a special reason for turning the tables in favour of bastardy; which is hinted at in this case。 The bastard's parents could not be produced against a bastard。 He ha
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!