按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
the rights themselves from the terms in which they happened to be expressed。 When one estate was said to be enslaved to another; or a right of way was said to be a quality or '383' incident of a neighboring piece of land; men's minds were not alert to see that these phrases were only so many personifying metaphors; which explained nothing unless the figure of speech was true。
Rogron deduced the negative nature of servitudes from the rule that the land owes the services; not the person;Proedium non persona servit。 For; said Rogron; the land alone being bound; it can only be bound passively。 Austin called this an 〃absurd remark。〃 /1/ But the jurists from whom we have inherited our law of easements were contented with no better reasoning。 Papinian himself wrote that servitudes cannot be partially extinguished; because they are due from lands; not persons。 /2/ Celsus thus decides the case which I took for my illustration: Even if possession of a dominant estate is acquired by forcibly ejecting the owner; the way will be retained; since the estate is possessed in such quality and condition as it is when taken。 /3/ The commentator Godefroi tersely adds that there are two such conditions; slavery and freedom; and his antithesis is as old as Cicero。 /4/ So; in another passage; Celsus asks; What else are the rights attaching to land but qualities of that land? /5/ So Justinian's Institutes speak of servitudes which inhere in buildings。 /6/ So Paulus '384' speaks of such rights as being accessory to bodies。 〃And thus;〃 adds Godefroi; 〃rights may belong to inanimate things。〃 /1/ It easily followed from all this that a sale of the dominant estate carried existing easements; not because the buyer succeeded to the place of the seller; but because land is bound to land。 /2/
All these figures import that land is capable of having rights; as Austin recognizes。 Indeed; he even says that the land 〃is erected into a legal or fictitious person; and is styled 'praedium dominans。'〃 /3/ But if this means anything more than to explain what is implied by the Roman metaphors; it goes too far。 The dominant estate was never 〃erected into a legal person;〃 either by conscious fiction or as a result of primitive beliefs。 /4/ It could not sue or be sued; like a ship in the admiralty。 It is not supposed that its possessor could maintain an action for an interference with an easement before his time; as an heir could for an injury to property of the hereditas jacens。 If land had even been systematically treated as capable of acquiring rights; the time of a disseisee might have been added to that Of the wrongful occupant; on the ground that the land; and not this or that individual; was gaining the easement; and that long association between the enjoyment of the privilege and the land was sufficient; which has never been the law。
All that can be said is; that the metaphors and similes employed naturally led to the rule which has prevailed; '385' and that; as this rule was just as good as any other; or at least was unobjectionable; it was drawn from the figures of speech without attracting attention; and before any one had seen that they were only figures; which proved nothing and justified no conclusion。
As easements were said to belong to the dominant estate; it followed that whoever possessed the land had a right of the same degree over what was incidental to it。 If the true meaning had been that a way or other easement admits of possession; and is taken possession of with the land to which it runs; and that its enjoyment is protected on the same grounds as possession in other cases; the thought could have been understood。 But that was not the meaning of the Roman law; and; as has been shown; it is not the doctrine of ours。 We must take it that easements have become an incident of land by an unconscious and unreasoned assumption that a piece of land can have rights。 It need not be said that this is absurd; although the rules of law which are based upon it are not so。
Absurd or not; the similes as well as the principles of the Roman law reappear in Bracton。 He says; 〃The servitude by which land is subjected to 'other' land; is made on the likeness of that by which man is made the slave of man。〃 /1/ For rights belong to a free tenement; as well as tangible things。。。。 They may be called rights or liberties with regard to the tenements to which they are owed; but servitudes with regard to the tenements by which they are owed 。。。。 One estate is free; the other subjected to slavery。〃 /2/ 〃'A servitude' may be called an arrangement by which house is subjected to house; farm to '386' farm; holding to holding。〃 /1/ No passage has met my eye in which Bracton expressly decides that an easement goes with the dominant estate upon a disseisin; but what he says leaves little doubt that he followed the Roman law in this as in other things。
The writ against a disseisor was for 〃so much land and its appurtenances;〃 /2/ which must mean that he who had the land even wrongfully had the appurtenances。 So Bracton says an action is in rem 〃whether it is for the principal thing; or for a right which adheres to the thing; 。。。 as when one sues for a right of way; 。。。 since rights of this sort are all incorporeal things; and are quasi possessed and reside in bodies; and cannot be got or kept without the bodies in which they inhere; nor in any way had without the bodies to which they belong。〃 /3/ And again; 〃Since rights do not admit of delivery; but are transferred with the thing in which they are; that is; the bodily thing; he to whom they are transferred forthwith has a quasi possession of those rights as soon as he has the body in which they are。〃 /4/
There is no doubt about the later law; as has been said at the outset。
We have thus traced two competing and mutually inconsistent principles into our law。 On the one hand is the conception of succession or privity; on the other; that of rights inhering in a thing。 Bracton seems to have vacillated a little from a feeling of the possibility of conflict between the two。 The benefit of a warranty was confined to those who; by the act and consent of the '387' grantee; succeeded to his place。 It did not pass to assigns unless assigns were mentioned。 Bracton supposes grants of easements with or without mention of assigns; which looks as if he thought the difference might be material with regard to easements also。 He further says; that if an easement be granted to A; his heirs and assigns; all such by the form of the grant are allowed the use in succession; and all others are wholly excluded。 /1/ But he is not speaking of what the rights of a disseisor would be as against one not having a better title; and he immediately adds that they are rights over a corporeal object belonging to a corporeal object。
Although it may be doubted whether the mention of assigns was ever necessary to attach an easement to land; and although it is very certain that it did not remain so long; the difficulty referred to grew greater as time went on。 It would have been easily disposed of if the only rights which could be annexed to land were easements; such as a right of way。 It then might have been said that these were certain limited interests