按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
iral claimed a forfeiture of ships for causing death。 I am bound to say; however; that I cannot find such an authority of that date。
We have now followed the development of the chief forms of liability in modern law for anything other than the immediate and manifest consequences of a man's own acts。 We have seen the parallel course of events in the two parents;the Roman law and the German customs; and in the offspring of those two on English soil with regard to servants; animals; and inanimate things。 We have seen a single germ multiplying and branching into products as different from each other as the flower from the root。 It hardly remains to ask what that germ was。 We have seen that it was the desire of retaliation against the offending thing itself。 Undoubtedly; it might be argued that many of the rules stated were derived from a seizure of the offending thing as security for reparation; at first; perhaps; outside the law。 That explanation; as well as the one offered here; would show that modern views of responsibility had not yet been attained; as the owner of the thing might very well not have been the person in fault。 But such has not been the view of those most competent to judge。 A consideration of the earliest instances will show; as might have been expected; that vengeance; not compensation; and vengeance on the offending thing; was the original object。 The ox in Exodus was to be stoned。 The axe in the Athenian law was to be banished。 The tree; in Mr。 Tylor's instance; was to be chopped to pieces。 The '35' slave under all the systems was to be surrendered to the relatives of the slain man; that they might do with him what they liked。 /1/ The deodand was an accursed thing。 The original limitation of liability to surrender; when the owner was before the court; could not be accounted for if it was his liability; and not that of his property; which was in question。 Even where; as in some of the cases; expiation seems to be intended rather than vengeance; the object is equally remote from an extrajudicial distress。
The foregoing history; apart from the purposes for which it has been given; well illustrates the paradox of form and substance in the development of law。 In form its growth is logical。 The official theory is that each new decision follows syllogistically from existing precedents。 But just as the clavicle in the cat only tells of the existence of some earlier creature to which a collar…bone was useful; precedents survive in the law long after the use they once served is at an end and the reason for them has been forgotten。 The result of following them must often be failure and confusion from the merely logical point of view。
On the other hand; in substance the growth of the law is legislative。 And this in a deeper sense than that what the courts declare to have always been the law is in fact new。 It is legislative in its grounds。 The very considerations which judges most rarely mention; and always with an apology; are the secret root from which the law draws all the juices of life。 I mean; of course; considerations of what is expedient for the community concerned。 Every important principle which is developed by litigation is in fact and at bottom the result of more or less definitely understood views of public policy; most generally; to be sure; '36' under our practice and traditions; the unconscious result of instinctive preferences and inarticulate convictions; but none the less traceable to views of public policy in the last analysis。 And as the law is administered by able and experienced men; who know too much to sacrifice good sense to a syllogism; it will be found that; when ancient rules maintain themselves in the way that has been and will be shown in this book; new reasons more fitted to the time have been found for them; and that they gradually receive a new content; and at last a new form; from the grounds to which they have been transplanted。
But hitherto this process has been largely unconscious。 It is important; on that account; to bring to mind what the actual course of events has been。 If it were only to insist on a more conscious recognition of the legislative function of the courts; as just explained; it would be useful; as we shall see more clearly further on。 /1/
What has been said will explain the failure of all theories which consider the law only from its formal side; whether they attempt to deduce the corpus from a priori postulates; or fall into the humbler error of supposing the science of the law to reside in the elegantia juris; or logical cohesion of part with part。 The truth is; that the law always approaching; and never reaching; consistency。 It is forever adopting new principles from life at one end; and it always retains old ones from history at the other; which have not yet been absorbed or sloughed off。 It will be come entirely consistent only when it ceases to grow。
The study upon which we have been engaged is necessary both for the knowledge and for the revision of the law。 '37' However much we may codify the law into a series of seemingly self…sufficient propositions; those propositions will be but a phase in a continuous growth。 To understand their scope fully; to know how they will be dealt with by judges trained in the past which the law embodies; we must ourselves know something of that past。 The history of what the law has been is necessary to the knowledge of what the law is。
Again; the process which I have described has involved the attempt to follow precedents; as well as to give a good reason for them。 When we find that in large and important branches of the law the various grounds of policy on which the various rules have been justified are later inventions to account for what are in fact survivals from more primitive times; we have a right to reconsider the popular reasons; and; taking a broader view of the field; to decide anew whether those reasons are satisfactory。 They may be; notwithstanding the manner of their appearance。 If truth were not often suggested by error; if old implements could not be adjusted to new uses; human progress would be slow。 But scrutiny and revision are justified。
But none of the foregoing considerations; nor the purpose of showing the materials for anthropology contained in the history of the law; are the immediate object here。 My aim and purpose have been to show that the various forms of liability known to modern law spring from the common ground of revenge。 In the sphere of contract the fact will hardly be material outside the cases which have been stated in this Lecture。 But in the criminal law and the law of torts it is of the first importance。 It shows that they have started from a moral basis; from the thought that some one was to blame。
'38' It remains to be proved that; while the terminology of morals is still retained; and while the law does still and always; in a certain sense; measure legal liability by moral standards; it nevertheless; by the very necessity of its nature; is continually transmuting those moral standards into external or objective ones; from which the actual guilt of the party concerned is wholly eliminated。
LECTURE II。
THE CRIMINAL LAW。
In the beginning of the first Lectur